Kant’s
Criticism of Swedenborg:Parapsychology
and the Origin of the Copernican Hypothesis
Prof. Stephen Palmquist, D.Phil. (Oxon)
Department of Religion and Philosophy
Hong Kong Baptist University
Human
reason was not givenstrong enough wings to part clouds so high above us, which
withhold from oureyes the secrets of the other world.[1]
1. The Traditional Myth of Kant’s‘Awakening’
Kant’slife
is traditionally portrayed as falling into two rather distinct periods.The
years prior to 1770 form the ‘pre-Critical’ period, while thosefrom 1770
onwards form the ‘Critical’ period. The turning-point isplaced in the year 1770
because this is when Kant wrote the Inaugural Dissertationfor his newly gained
position as Professor of Logic and Metaphysics at theUniversity of Koenigsberg.
In this work, entitled On the Form and Principlesof the Sensible and
Intelligible World,[2] he proposed for the first
time that space andtime should be regarded as "forms of intuition"
that human subjectsread into experience, rather than as self-subsisting
attributes of nature that weread out from the objects we experience. The
typical‘textbook’ account of Kant’s life usually declares that
the‘pre-Critical’ Kant was a Leibnizian dogmatist, trained in theschool of
Wolffian rationalism, and was interested as much in natural scienceas in
philosophy, but that sometime around 1770 Kant was suddenly"awakened"
from his "dogmatic slumbers" by his reflectionon David Hume’s
philosophy.[3] Some commentators, such as Kuehn (1983),go so far as to say not
only that "Kant and Hume aim at the very samething", but that
"all the specific doctrines of Kant’s criticalenterprise are intimately
bound up with Hume’s influence on Kant."(p.191)
Althoughit
is difficult to determine the exact nature and date of this dramaticawakening,
there is no doubt that Kant was familiar with Hume’s ideas bythe early 1760s;
indeed, so the story goes, in 1766 he published a book thatadopts Hume’s
empiricist standpoint almost completely.[4] This book,entitled Dreams of a
Spirit-Seer, Illustrated by Dreams of Metaphysics [hereafter Dreams],
is typicallyinterpreted as a minor work of an exceedingly skeptical nature, and
ofrelatively little importance in understanding Kant’s mature thought.
This"strangest and most tortured of Kant’s writings"(Ward 1972,p.34)
is, at best, a stage he passed out of as quickly as he passed into it,and at
worst, an embarrassment for Kant and Kant scholars alike. The
embarrassmentcould come not only as a result of the rather unorthodox
subject-matter –what we would now call parapsychology (i.e., studying
the nature ofvisions and various types of mystical experiences – but because of
theflippant attitude Kant adopts from time to time throughout the book (see
note25, below). Indeed, regardless of how we interpret the philosophical
content ofthis book, the psychological disposition of its author, who had
recentlyentered his fifth decade, would appear to be that of a man in the midst
of whatwe might nowadays call a mid-life crisis.[5]
Thetraditional
account contains at least as much error as truth. While it is truethat Kant
never mentions his mature theory of the transcendental ideality ofspace and
time before 1770, it is not true that he owes the theory to Hume(whose
theory of space and time bears little resemblance to Kant’s). Noris it
legitimate to equate this doctrine (expounded in its official form in
theAesthetic of the first Critique) with the term ‘Critical’, as is
impliedby the dating of the Critical period from 1770. On the contrary,
Kantassociates his "new method of thought, namely, that we can know apriori
of things only what we ourselves put into them", not with the Criticalmethod,
but with the new ‘Copernican’ insight he believes willenable him to
revolutionize philosophy.[6] His description and use
of Criticismas a philosophical method is quite distinct from its application to
problems inmetaphysics by means of the Copernican hypothesis. Thus, when Kant
instructedthe editor of his minor writings to ignore all those written before
1770, (seeSewall 1900, p.x) he was not defining the starting point of his
application ofthe Critical method, but rather that of his application of the
Copernican hypothesisto the task of constructing a new philosophical System. If
we must divide hislife into two periods at 1770, we should therefore avoid
using the term‘pre-Critical’ (as others have advised, but without giving a
viablealternative [e.g., Beiser 1992, p.36; Dell’Oro 1994, p.174]) and
referinstead to the ‘pre-Copernican’ and ‘Copernican’periods. Adopting this new
label will protect us from making inconsistentstatements such as Gulick’s
(1994), implicitly conflating these two formsof revolution: "Kant’s
self-designated Copernican revolution usheredin his critical period" (p.99).
Since Kant exhibited ‘Critical’ tendencies throughout hislife, his mature years
should be named the ‘Copernican’ period.
Beforewe
proceed it is crucial to have a thorough understanding of Kant’smature
conception of ‘Criticism’ or ‘Critique’ (Kritik), as elaboratedin CPR.
In the first edition Preface, Kant describes his era as "the ageof
criticism", during which reason accords "sincere respect ... onlyto
that which has been able to sustain the test of free and openexamination"
(CPR, Axin). But this enlightened "habit ofthought" can be
trusted only if it submits to its own "tribunal"of Criticism
(Axi-xii). Thus "the subject-matter of our criticalenquiry" (i.e., of
the entire Critical philosophy) is reason itself(Axiv),
and its "first task" is "to discover the sources andconditions
of the possibility of such criticism" (Axxi). This means thequestions
addressed to reason cannot be answered by means of
…a
dogmatic and visionaryinsistence upon knowledge ... that can be catered
for only through magicaldevices, in which I am no adept. Such ways of answering them are, indeed, notwithin
the intention of the natural constitution of our reason; and ... it is theduty
of philosophy to counteract their deceptive influence, no matter whatprized and
cherished dreams may have to bedisowned.(CPR, Ap.xiii, emphasis
added)[7]
Instead, only by first examining "the very
natureof knowledge itself" can we answer reason’s questions in such a
wayas to provide solutions to the problems of metaphysics (Ap.xiii-xiv).
Inthe
second edition Preface Kant not only describes more fully thesubject-matter of
the particular type of Critique he plans to engage in, butalso explains more
clearly the nature of the Critical method. Metaphysics willbe "purified by
criticism and established once for all": thepurification is "merely negative,
warning us that we must neverventure with speculative reason beyond the limits
of experience"; but theestablishment is positive inasmuch as it
"removes an obstacle which standsin the way of the employment of practical
reason" (CPR, p.xxiv-xxv). Inother words, the scope of
reason’s speculative (i.e., theoretical)standpoint is
narrowed by tying it to sensibility, but this frees metaphysicsto be
established on the firmer foundation of reason’s practicalstandpoint — i.e., on
morality (p.xv). The Critical method,therefore,
is intended to establish limits, but to do so for both negative andpositive
purposes. The former can be seen when Kant refers to "ourcritical
distinction between two modes of representation, the sensible and
theintellectual" and immediately adds "and of the resulting
limitation..."; (CPR, p.xxviii)[8]
likewise, he argues thatnon-contradictory doctrines of freedom and morality are
"possible only inso far as criticism ... has limited all that we can theoretically
know to mereappearances" (p.xxix). The positive benefit of such
limitations is thatthey enable us to avoid "dogmatism" (defined here
as "thepreconception that it is possible to make headway in metaphysics
without aprevious criticism of pure reason"), which "is the source of
all that[skeptical] unbelief ... which wars against
morality" (p.xxx). Indeed,Kant goes so far as to
say that "all objections to morality and religionwill be for ever
silenced" (p.xxxi), because his Critique will "severthe root of materialism,
fatalism, atheism, free-thinking, fanaticism, and superstition ...
as well asof idealism and scepticism" (p.xxxiv).
Throughoutthe
rest of CPR Kant repeats many of these same claims about thenature of
Criticism in its special, philosophical form. In most of theiroccurrences the
words ‘critical’, ‘criticism’, and‘critique’ are used in close connection with
some mention of the limitations of knowledge.[9]The only interesting
exception is that on several occasions he adds thatCriticism serves as a
middle way between the opposite extremes of dogmatism andskepticism (CPR
22-3, A388-9, 784-5, 789, 797). Indeed, thisepitomizes Kant’s association
of the Critical method with synthesis, which he claimsalways takes the triadic
form of "(1) a condition, (2) a conditioned, (3)the
concept arising from the union of the conditioned with its condition"(CJ,
p.179n). And of course, the most
basic exampleof his use of this pattern is his exposition of the Critical
philosophy in theform of three Critiques.
Thisbrief
analysis of Kant’s understanding of the Critical method revealsthat he never
associates it directly with the Copernican hypothesis but,instead,
with several key distinctions. The Critical method is, for Kant, themethod of
striking a middle way between two extremes ("a third step",as he
calls it in CPR 789 [see also 177, 194, 196, 264, 315, 760-1, 794]).It
operates by trying to locate the boundary between what can be known (and proved)
and what cannever be known (yet remains possible) — the boundary line
beingdefined in terms of "the limits of all possible experience"
(e.g.,p.121). Thus it is closely associated with "the distinction between
thetranscendental and the empirical" (p.81), as well as with that betweenspeculative
(theoretical) and practical (moral) "employments of reason",or standpoints.[10] Although certain apparently
skeptical claimshave to be made on the way, the ultimate purpose of Criticism
for Kant ispositive: to provide a means of constructing the foundation for
metaphysicsupon solid (non-speculative, moral) grounds.
Acareful
reading of Kant’s works reveals that traces of this Critical wayof doing
philosophy are evident throughout most of his writings, from theearliest essays
on metaphysics and natural philosophy to the latest essays onreligion,
political history, and other subjects.[11] Indeed, the fact that he uses this
method todevelop and expound the implications of his Copernican hypothesis is
what giveslasting value to the theories that arise out of it, and not vice
versa. There is noneed to provide here a thoroughgoing proof of the
ubiquity of the Criticalmethod in Kant’s writings.(for
this see KSP, II.2, pp.32,39, passim). Instead I shallconcentrate on Dreams
because, in proportion to its importance, it is themost neglected and/or
misunderstood book in the corpus of Kant’swritings. The next section sketches
the contents of this book, after which Ishall draw attention in §3 to its
Critical character and discuss its rolein Kant’s discovery of the Copernican
hypothesis. Finally, I shall offersome brief suggestions in §4 as to the
relation between Dreams and Kant’smature System of Perspectives. In so
doing we shall find that Kant’sassessment of Swedenborg and his unusual
experiences was far from beingentirely negative; on the contrary, it provides
us with a level of insight intothe nature and limits of parapsychology that is
highly appropriate for aFestschrift honoring John Beloff, one of the most
respected contemporaryphilosophical researchers into the mysteries of this
topic that fascinated Kantso much.
2. Kant’s Criticism of Swedenborg’sMystical Dreams
InDreams
Kant examines the nature and possibility of mystical visions, payingspecial
attention to the claims of a Swedish writer and accomplished scientistnamed
Emanuel Swedenborg.[12] Kantexamines these visions not only to
explore the limits of his own commitment toa belief in the spirit world,[13]
but also (and more importantly) in order todraw attention to the dangers of
speculative metaphysics by comparing it withfanatical mysticism. This analogy,
present as it is in the very title of thework, will prove to be of utmost
importance in understanding how Dreams relates to thelater development
of Kant’s System. As noted earlier, Dreams is commonlyinterpreted as
evidence of a radically empiricist stage in Kant’sdevelopment, where he is
supposedly adopting something of a Humean position.But his actual intention, as
we shall see, is to encourage a Critical attitude: whilehe comes down
hard on the misuse of reason by spirit-seers and metaphysicianswhen they regard
their respective dreams "as a source ofknowledge"(Sewall 1900,
p.146), he expresses quite clearly his own dreamthat a properly balanced
approach to both mysticism and metaphysics willsomeday emerge.[14] A detailed
examination of Kant’s views onparapsychological phenomena as presented in Dreams
can thereforeprovide some helpful clues as to Kant’s motivations for
constructing theCritical philosophy itself.
Themystical
experiences considered in Dreams are not experiences of the presenceof
God (i.e., "of infinite spirit which is originator and preserver of
theuniverse" (Dreams p.321n[44n]), but
experiences of lower spiritualbeings, who are supposed to be able to
communicate with earthly beings invisions and apparitions. Although Kant
ridicules those who have suchexperiences at several points in Dreams, he
reveals his private view ofsuch experiences in two important letters. In a
letter to Charlotte vonKnoblock (dated 10 August, probably 1763) he admits he
"always consideredit to be most in agreement with sound reason to incline
to the negative side..., until the report concerning Swedenborg came to my
notice" (Sewall1900, p.158).[15] After recounting
several impressive stories, Kant tells howSwedenborg was once able to describe
in precise detail a fire that "hadjust broken out in Stockholm", even
though he was fifty miles away inGöteborg. He says this "occurrence
appears to me to have the greatestweight of proof, and to place the assertion
respecting Swedenborg’sextraordinary gift beyond all possibility of
doubt."(Sewall 1900,p.158) In a subsequent letter (8April 1766) to
Mendelssohn Kant explains that he clothed his thoughts withridicule in Dreams
in order to avoid being ridiculed by otherphilosophers for paying attention to
mystical visions (hardly taken seriouslyby most philosophers in the
Enlightenment (see Dreams 353-4[91-2])).He admits:
…the
attitude ofmy own mind is inconsistent and, so far as these stories are
concerned, Icannot help having a slight inclination for things of this kind,
and indeed, asregards their reasonableness, I cannot help cherishing an opinion
that there issome validity in these experiences in spite of all the absurdities
involved inthe stories about them ...(Sewall 1900, p.162)
Elsewherein
the same letter he draws a Critical conclusion: "Neither
thepossibility nor the impossibility of this kind of thing can be proved, and
ifsomeone attacked Swedenborg’s dreams as impossible, I
shouldundertake to defend them." (Rabel 1963, p.74)[16] Clearly, Kant
believed somethingsignificant is happening in such parapsychological
experiences –significant enough to merit a comparison with the tasks of
metaphysics,"the dream science itself", to which he admits to being
hopelessly "inlove"(Zweig 1967, p.55; see also KCR I.2). The problem this set for him was to
describe "just whatkind of a thing that is about which these people think
they understand somuch" (Dreams p.319[41]).
Inthe
Preface to Dreams Kant hints at the Critical nature of his inquiry
byasking two opposing questions, but offering a "third way out":
heasks (1) "Shall [the philosopher] wholly deny the truth of all
theapparitions [eye-witnesses] tell about?"; or (2) "Shall he, on
theother hand, admit even one of these stories?"; and he answers that (3)
thephilosopher should "hold on to the useful"(p.317-8[38]).[17] The treatiseitself consists of seven
chapters, grouped in two parts: Part One contains four"dogmatic"
chapters and Part Two contains three"historical" chapters. The
correspondence between these two parts andthe structure of the System he was
soon to begin elaborating is evident by thefact that Part One ends with a
chapter on "Theoretical Conclusions"and Part Two ends with a chapter
on "Practical Conclusions" (Dreams pp.348[85],368[115]), thus
foreshadowing the division between the first and second Critiques.
Thetheoretical
part begins in Chapter One, under the heading "A complicatedmetaphysical
knot which can be untied or cut according to choice" (Dreams p.319[41]), bydiscussing what a spirit is or might
be. Kant confesses:
I do
not know if thereare spirits, yea, what is more, I do not even know what the
word‘spirit’ signifies. But, as I have often used it myself, and haveheard
others using it, something must be understood by it, be this somethingmere
fancy or reality. (p.320[42])
Tothis
rather Wittgensteinian remark he adds that "the conception ofspiritual
nature cannot be drawn from experience", though its
"hiddensense" can be drawn "out of its obscurity through a
comparison ofsundry cases of application" (p.320n[42-3n]).
He then argues that a spiritmust be conceived as a simple, immaterial being,
possessing reason as aninternal quality (pp.320-1[43-5]). After considering
some of the difficultiesassociated with this concept, he adopts an entirely
Critical position: "Thepossibility of the existence of immaterial
beings can ... be supposed without fearof its being disproved, but also without
hope of proving it by reason"(p.323[46-7],
emphasis added). If one assumes "that the soul of man is aspirit",
even though this cannot be proved, then the problem arises as tohow it is
connected with the body (pp.324-5[48-9]). Kant rejects the Cartesianfocus on a
mechanism in the brain in favor of "commonexperience":[18]
Nobody
... is consciousof occupying a separate place in his body, but only of that
place which heoccupies as a man in regard to the world around him. I would,
therefore, keepto common experience, and would say, provisionally, where I
sense, there I am.I am just as immediately in the tips of my fingers, as
in my head. It is myselfwho suffers in the heel and whose heart beats in
affection (Dreamspp.324-5[48-9]).[19]
Thechapter
concludes with the confession "that I am very much inclined toassert the
existence of immaterial natures in the world, and to put my soulinto that class
of beings" (p.327[52]). Although he concedes that
thevarious questions concerned with such a belief are "above
myintelligence" (p.328[54]), he does suggest in Dreams
that"Whatever in the world contains a principle of life, seems to
be ofimmaterial nature. For all life rests on the inner capacity [cf. freedom
in thesecond Critique] to determine one’s self by one’s ownwill
power." (p.327n[52-3n])
Afterconfirming
the metaphysical possibility of (and his personal belief in)spirits,
Kant presents in Chapter Two "a fragment of secret philosophyaiming to
establish communion with the spirit-world" (Dreams p.329[55]).
Hebegins by positing an "immaterial world" that is conceived "as
agreat whole, an immeasurable but unknown gradation of beings and active
naturesby which alone the dead matter of the corporeal world is endued
withlife." (Dreams p.330[57]).[20] As a
member of both the material and the immaterial world, a human being"forms
a personal unit" (p.332[60]). Kant conjectures that purelyimmaterial
beings may "flow into the souls of men as into beings of theirown nature,
and ... are actually at all times in mutual intercourse withthem", though
the results of such intercourse cannot ordinarily "becommunicated to the
other purely spiritual beings", nor "betransferred into the
consciousness of men" (p.333[61]). As evidence
forsuch a communion of spirits, Kant examines the nature of morality. Using one
ofhis favorite geometrical metaphors (that of intersecting lines), he says in Dreams (pp.334-5[63]):
"The point towhich the lines of direction of our impulses converge is ...
not only inourselves, but ... in the will of others outside of ourselves."
The factthat our actions are motivated not only by selfishness, but also by
duty andbenevolence, reveals that "we are dependent upon the rule of
the willof all" (p.335[64]); and "the
sensation of this dependence"– i.e., our "sense of morality" –
suggests that "thecommunity of all thinking beings" is governed by
"a moral unity, and asystematic constitution according to purely
spiritual laws." Thus,"because the morality of an action concerns the
inner state of thespirit", its effect can be fully realized not in the
empirical world, but"only in the immediate communion of spirits"(p.336[65]).
Inreply
to the possible objection that, given this view of the spirit-world,"the
scarcity of apparitions" seems "extraordinary", Kantstresses
that "the conceptions of the one world are not ideas associatedwith those
of the other world"; so even if we have a "clear andperspicuous"
spiritual conception, this cannot be regarded as "anobject of actual
[i.e., material] sight and experience." (Dreamspp.337-8[67-9]).[21] However, he freely admits that a person, being
bothmaterial and immaterial, can become
…conscious of theinfluences of the spirit-world even
in this life. For
spiritual ideas ... stirup those pictures which are related to them and awake
analogous ideas of oursenses. These, it is true, would not be spiritual
conceptions themselves, butyet their symbols.... Thus it is not improbable that
spiritual sensations canpass over into consciousness if they act upon
correlated ideas of the senses.(pp.338-9[69-70])
Even"our
higher concepts of reason" need to "clothe themselves"in,
"as it were, a bodily garment to make themselves clear", as
when"the geometrician represents time by a line" (p.339[69-70]).
Anactual apparition, which might "indicate a disease, because it
presupposesan altered balance of the nerves", is unusual because it is
based not on asimple metaphor, but on "a delusion of the
imagination", in which"a true spiritual influence" is perceived
in imagined "pictures... which assume the appearance of sensations"
(p.340[71]). Kant warns thatin an apparition "delusion is mingled with
truth", so it tends todeceive "in spite of the fact that such
chimeras may be based upon atrue spiritual influence" (p.340[71-2], emphasis added).
Intruly
Critical fashion Kant now adopts the opposite perspective in ChapterThree,
presenting an "Antikabala" – that is, "a fragmentof common
philosophy aiming to abolish communion with the spirit-world" (Dreams
p.342[74]). HereKant first states the analogy between metaphysicians("reason-dreamers") and visionaries
("sensation-dreamers"):in both cases the dreamer imagines a private
world "which no other healthyman sees", yet "both are
self-created pictures which neverthelessdeceive the senses as if they were true
objects" (pp.342-3[75]). In orderto help such dreamers "wake up, i.e.,
open their eyes to such a view asdoes not exclude conformity with other
people’s common sense"(p.342[74]), he proposes an
alternative description of what is happening in anapparition. The problem is to
explain how visionaries "place thephantoms of their imagination
outside of themselves, and even put them inrelation to their body, which they
sense through their external senses"(pp.343-4 [77]). He suggests that in
external sensation "our soul locatesthe perceived object at the point
where the different lines, indicating thedirection of the impression,
meet", whereas in a vision this "focusimaginarius" is
located not outside of the body but "inside of thebrain"
(pp.344-5[77-9]). The difference between the fantasy of a saneperson (see p.346n[81n]) and the delusions of an insane person is that
only thelatter "places mere objects of his imagination outside of himself,
andconsiders them to be real and present objects" (p.346[80]). So
"thedisease of the visionary concerns not so much the reason, as a
deception of thesenses" (p.347[82]). Kant
concludes that this simpler interpretation"renders entirely superfluous
the deep conjectures of the precedingchapter ... Indeed, from this perspective,
there was no need of going back asfar as to metaphysics" (pp.347-8[82-3]).[22]
Thefourth
and final chapter of Part One presents the "theoretical conclusionfrom the
whole of the consideration of the first part" (Dreams p.348[85]). Kantbegins with a penetrating description of his
own method of philosophizing(i.e., the Critical
method), according to which "the partiality of thescales of reason"
is always checked by letting "the merchandise andthe weights exchange
pans" (pp.348-9[85]). He uses this metaphor to maketwo points. First, it
suggests the importance of being willing to give up allprejudices:
I now
have nothing atheart; nothing is venerable to me but what enters by the path of
sincerity intoa quiet mind open to all reasons ... Whenever I meet with
somethinginstructive, I appropriate it.... Formerly, I viewed common sense only
from thestandpoint of my own; now I put myself into the position of a foreign
reasonoutside myself, and observe my judgments, together with their most
secretcauses, from the standpoint of others. (p.349[85-6])
Kant’s exposition in Dreams exemplifies
thisCritical (perspectival) shift by opposing the merchandise of his own
prejudicesconcerning the spirit-world (Chapter Two) with the dead weight of
areductionist explanation (Chapter Three). The second point of the analogy is,however, the crucial one: we must recognize that "The
scale of reason isnot quite impartial" and so move the merchandise from
the speculative panto the pan "bearing the inscription ‘Hope of the
Future’"(i.e., from the standpoint of the first Critique to that of
thethird[23]), where "even those light reasons ... outweigh the
speculationsof greater weight on the other side" (Dreams
p.349[86]). Hereat the threshold of his mature philosophical System, then, Kant
stresses theoverriding importance of what I call the ‘judicial’ standpoint
(seenote 23): "This is the only inaccuracy [of the scales of reason] which
Icannot easily remove, and which, in fact, I never want to
remove"(pp.349-50[86]).
Onthis
basis Kant concludes that, even though "in the scale of speculationthey
seem to consist of nothing but air", the dreams of spirit-seers
(andmetaphysicians!) "have appreciable weight only in the scale of hope"
(Dreams p.350[86-7]).While admitting "that I do not understand a
single thing about the wholematter" of how the immaterial can interact
with the material, he claims"that this study ... exhausts all
philosophical knowledge about[spiritual] beings ... in the negative sense, by
fixing with assurance thelimits of our knowledge" (pp.349-50[88-9]). The
assumed spiritualprinciple of life "can never be thought of in a positive
way, because forthis purpose no data can be found in the whole of our
sensations"(pp.351-2[89]).[24] He is therefore constrained by ignorance to
"deny thetruth of the various ghost stories", yet he maintains
"a certainfaith in the whole of them taken together" (p.351[88]).[25]
As I haveargued elsewhere (KSP, V.1), this subordination of speculative
knowledge topractical faith is the key to the justification of the Copernican
Perspectiveitself. Thus, when Kant concludes Part One by saying "this
whole matter ofspirits" will "not concern me any more", because
"I hope tobe able to apply to better advantage my small reasoning powers
upon othersubjects" (p.352[90]), he may be hinting that he is already
beginning toformulate a plan for constructing a System of Perspectives based on
Criticalreasoning.
Havingpromised
not to philosophize on spirits any longer, Kant recounts in the firstchapter of
the second ("historical") part three stories concerningthe spiritual
powers of Swedenborg, "the truth of which the reader isrecommended to
investigate as he likes" (Dreams p.353[91]). Heclaims
"absolute indifference to the kind or unkind judgment of thereader",
admitting that in any case "stories of this kind will have... only secret
believers, while publicly they are rejected by the prevalentfashion of
disbelief" (pp.353-4[92]).
Inthe
second chapter of Part Two Kant provides a summary of Swedenborg’sown
explanation of his "ecstatic journey through the world ofspirits" (Dreams
p.357[98]) and notes its similarity to
"theadventure which, in the foregoing [i.e., in Part One], we have
undertaken inthe balloon of metaphysics" (p.360[102]). The position
Swedenborg develops"resembles so uncommonly the philosophical creation of
my own brain",Kant explains, that he feels the
need to "declare ... that in regard tothe alleged examples I mean no
joke" (p.359[100]). To cover up his owninterest in Swedenborg’s work, Kant
ridicules his ‘hero’ forwriting an eight-volume work "utterly empty of the
last drop ofreason" (pp.359-60[101]) – a good example of the occasional
harsh orfrivolous statements that later embarrassed him (see note 16). The
extractturns out to be so close to the views Kant had expounded in Chapter Two
of PartOne that he concludes his summary by reassuring the reader that "I
havenot substituted my own fancies for those of our author, but have offered
hisviews in a faithful extract to the comfortable and economic reader who does
notcare to sacrifice seven pounds [closer to seven hundred these days!] fora little curiosity" (p.366[111]).
Thechapter
ends with an apology for leading the reader "by a tiresomeroundabout way
to the same point of ignorance from which he started", butadds that "I
have wasted my time that I might gain it. I have deceived thereader so that I
might be of use to him" (Dreams p.367-8[112-3]).After confessing
his unrequited love of metaphysics, Kant insists thatmetaphysics as a rational
inquiry "into the hidden qualities ofthings" (i.e., speculative
metaphysics) must be clearly distinguished from"metaphysics [as] the
science of the boundaries of human reason"(i.e., Critical
metaphysics):
Before
... we had flownon the butterfly-wings of metaphysics, and there conversed with
spiritualbeings. Now ... we find ourselves again on the ground of experience
and commonsense. Happy, if we look at it as the place allotted to us, which we
can leave withimpunity, and which contains everything to satisfy us as long as
we hold fastto the useful. (p.368[114])
Far from indicating a temporary conversion
fromdogmatic rationalism to skeptical empiricism, as is usually assumed about Dreams,
this passage, interpretedin its proper context, reveals that Kant already has a
clear conception of theCritical method, and is nurturing the seed that
was to grow into hiscomplete philosophical System.
Anydoubt
about the Critical character of Dreams is dispelled bythe
"practical conclusion from the whole treatise" given in the
finalchapter of Part Two (p.368[115]). Kant begins by
distinguishing between whatscience can understand to achieve knowledge
and what reason needs to understand toachieve wisdom – a
distinction that pervades the entirety ofhis mature System. By determining what
is impossible to know, science canestablish "the limits set to human
reason by nature", so that"even metaphysics will become ... the
companion of wisdom" (p.368[115-6]).He then introduces (what I call) the
principle of perspective as the guidingprinciple of this new way of philosophizing:
once philosophy "judges itsown proceedings, and ... knows not only
objects, but their relation toman’s reason", thus establishing the perspective
from which theobject is viewed, "then ... the boundary stones are laid
which in futurenever allow investigation to wander beyond its proper
district"(pp.368-9[116], emphasis added). This is followed by a warning
against thefailure to distinguish between philosophical relations (i.e., those
known byreflection) and "fundamental relations" (i.e., those that
"mustbe taken from experience alone") – the distinction that forms
thebasis for all other Critical distinctions.[26] That Kant is here referring
toimmediate experience, not to empirical knowledge, is evident when he
says"I know that will and understanding move my body, but I can never
reduceby analysis this phenomenon, as a simple [immediate] experience, to
anotherexperience, and can, therefore, indeed recognize it, but not
understandit" (p.369 [117]). He reaffirms that our powers of reflection provide"good
reason to conceive of an incorporeal and constant being"; butbecause our
immediate experience as earthly beings relating to other earthlybeings depends
on "corporeal laws", we can never know for certainwhat
"spiritual" laws would hold if we were "to think ...without
connection with a body" (pp.370-1[117-8]). The possibility ofestablishing
"new fundamental relations of cause and effect" –i.e., of having an
immediate experience not of corporeal nature but ofspiritual nature – "can
never ... be ascertained"; the"creative genius or ... chimera,
whichever you like to call it",which invents such spiritual (later called
noumenal) causality cannot establishknowledge (much less scientific ‘proof’)
precisely because the"pretended experiences" are not governed by corporeal
(later called apriori) laws, which alone are required for a
knowledge-claim to be"unanimously accepted by men" (pp.371-2[118-9]).
Thisfinal
chapter of Dreams ends with a concise (and entirely Critical)explanation of the positive aspect of this otherwise
negative conclusion. Thefact that "philosophic knowledge is impossible in
the case underconsideration" need cause no concern (neither for the
metaphysician norfor the mystic) as long as we recognize that "such
knowledge isdispensable and unnecessary", because reason does not need to
know suchthings (p.372[120]). "The vanity of
science" fools us into believingthat "a proof from experience of the
existence of such things" isrequired. "But true wisdom is the
companion of simplicity, and as, withthe latter, the
heart rules the understanding, it generally renders unnecessarythe great
preparations of scholars, and its aims do not need such means as cannever be at
the command of all men." The true philosophy, which Kantalways believed
would confirm common sense and therefore would be attainablefor everyone
(unlike a speculative dependence on theoretical proofs or mysticalapparitions,
each available to only a few individuals), should be based on"immediate
moral precepts" — that is, on a "moralfaith" that "guides
[the ‘righteous soul’] to his trueaims" (pp.372-3[120-1]). Thus he
concludes (p.373 [121]) by defending theposition later elaborated in his
practical and religious systems, that it ismore appropriate ‘to base the
expectation of a future world upon thesentiment of a good soul, than,
conversely, to base the soul’s goodconduct upon the hope of another world.’
3. Kant’s Four Major ‘Awakenings’
Inthe
preceding section we have seen that all the main characteristics ofKant’s
Critical method, together with anticipations of several of hismature doctrines
and distinctions, are present in Dreams. The method of choosingthe
middle path between two extremes is exemplified by Kant’s advice inthe Preface
to "hold on to the useful" — though this is notexactly how he would
later describe his Critical means of steering between theextremes of dogmatism
and skepticism [but cf. note 17]. The Criticaldistinction between the
theoretical and the practical, whose most obviousapplication is to the
distinction between the first two Critiques, is foreshadowedby the
conclusions to the two parts of Dreams, the first beingtheoretical and
the second, practical. The attitude expressed in the firstchapter, that
‘spirits’ are theoretically possible but can never beproved to exist, is reminiscent
of the hypothetical perspective adopted in theDialectic of CPR, where
all ‘ideas of reason’ are treatedsimilarly.[27]
Eventhe
second chapter, where Kant is letting his metaphysical imagination runwild,
contains an interesting parallel: Kant’s suggestion that the innerstate of
spirits is primarily important in its connection with morality is
entirelyconsistent with his later decision to regard morality as the proper
foundationfor metaphysics. (The same point is emphasized in the last chapter,
where thetrue basis for belief in spirits is said to rest on morality rather
thanspeculation.) And the skepticism Kant adopts in Chapter Three is not unlike
theversion he sometimes adopts in the Dialectic of the first Critique
(in both casesas a temporary measure to guard against unwarranted speculation).[28] Thesubordination of the theoretical (i.e.,
speculative) to the practical and thejudicial (see note 23), as hinted by
Kant’s expressed preference for the"useful", is forcefully emphasized
by his reference to the"scales of reason" in the fourth chapter. His
use of this metaphor toemphasize the philosophical legitimacy of hope for the
future in spite of ourtheoretical ignorance foreshadows both the third Critique
and Religion.[29] ThroughoutPart One, and again
in the second chapter of Part Two, Kant describes his newview of the first and
foremost task of metaphysics in exactly the same terms ashe would use some
fifteen years later in CPR: metaphysicsmust begin as a negative science
concerned with establishing the limits ofknowledge. And in the book’s final
chapter we meet not only thedistinction between immediate experience and
reflective knowledge, which is socrucial to Kant’s System [see note 26], but
also the equally importantnotion that reason does not need to have a theoretical
understanding ofmystical experiences (or metaphysical propositions), as long as
we take intoconsideration the common moral awareness of all human beings.
IfKant
was in full possession of the Critical method by 1766, why, it might beasked,
did he take fifteen more years to write CPR? This is
particularlyperplexing in light of the fact that after 1781 Kant published at
least onemajor work nearly every year until 1798. The typical explanation
ofKant’s development renders this problem slightly less difficult, becausethe
‘Critical awakening’ is regarded as not happening
until thelate 1760s or early 1770s. On this view Kant had a great deal of
troubleformulating his ideas for CPR, yet after it was completed
he suddenlyrealized the need for a second Critique, and after
that, the needfor a third. However, the fact that Kant could apply all the
Critical tools in1766 to write Dreams makes it very difficult to believe
that he wouldfumble around for fifteen more years, and then suddenly turn into
a prolificgenius. Rather, it suggests Kant may well have wanted to have the basic(architectonic) plan for his entire System more or less
complete in his mind before even starting the long task
ofcommitting it to paper. The need for a fifteen year gap (including his
long‘silent decade’) between Dreams and CPR becomes
moreunderstandable if we regard Kant as formulating in his mind during this
timenot just CPR, but his entire System — though obviously, thedetails
concerning the precise form it would take had not entirely crystallizedby
1781.[30] The traditional viewfails
to take account of the fact that writers do not always say everythingthey know
about their plans for future undertakings, and also ignores theimportance of Kant’s
emphasis on establishing and maintaining specificarchitectonic patterns.[31]
Theone
aspect of Kant’s transcendental philosophy that is conspicuouslyabsent in Dreams
is the cornerstone of the whole System, the Copernican hypothesis(i.e., the assumption that a posteriori
objectivity is based on a priori subjectivity,rather than vice versa
[see KSP, III.1]). And this had begun to dawn on him by 1770,when he wrote Dissertation, where he regards time
and space as "forms ofintuition" not inherent in the object itself.
Thus the crucial questionis: if ‘Criticism’ was the original distinguishing
character ofKant’s life-long philosophical method, what was the source of the
suddeninsight he later called his ‘Copernican’ hypothesis? Copleston(1960,
p.196) conjectures that the new insight might have come as a result ofhis
reading of the Clarke-Leibniz Correspondence, newly publishedin
1768. Others would cite Hume
asresponsible for all such major changes in Kant’s position (see e.g., note4).
What has long been ignored in English Kant-scholarship is the significantextent
to which some of the details of the Critical philosophy, not the leastbeing the
Copernican hypothesis itself, actually correspond to
the ideasdeveloped by Swedenborg. Kant himself acknowledges this correspondence
to someextent in Dreams, but repeatedly emphasizes that the ideas he
presentsas his own were developed independently of his acquaintance
withSwedenborg’s writings (Dreams p.359 [100], p.360[102],
p.366[111]). However, theextent of the parallels between his subsequent
theories (especiallythose in Dissertation) and Swedenborg’s is
sufficient to merit theassumption that, in spite of his ridicule in Dreams,
Kant actuallyadopted much of Swedenborg’s ‘nonsense’ (p.360[101]) into hisown
thinking (see Dreams pp.357-8[98-9]; Sewall 1900, pp.24-7, 31-3)!
Agood
example of the similarity between Kant’s mature views andSwedenborg’s ideas is
brought out in Kant’s summary ofSwedenborg’s position, highlighting the
distinction between athing’s true or ‘inner’ meaning and its outer
manifestation.How closely this coincides with the position Kant eventually
defends in hiswritings on religion becomes quite clear in Dreams when he
says:"This inner meaning ... is the origin of all the new interpretations which[Swedenborg] would make of the Scripture. For this
inner meaning, the internalsense, i.e., the symbolic relation of all things
told there to thespirit-world, is, as he fancies, the kernel of its value, the
rest only theshell" (p.364[108]).
As Iargue elsewhere (KCR, VI.2), Kant uses precisely the same
metaphor in hisown investigation of "pure religion", except that the
"innermeaning" is derived from practical reflection (the Critical
mode ofdreaming?) rather than from visionary "dreams" about the
spirit-world.
Amore
detailed examination of Swedenborg’s epistemological distinctionswould reveal
numerous other corresponding theories. For example, the Copernicanassumption
itself, which marks the main difference between Dreams and Dissertation,
has its rootsat least partially in Swedenborg. For, as Vaihinger puts it, the
relationshipof Kant’s "transcendental subject ... to the Spiritual Ego
ofSwedenborg is unmistakable"; indeed Kant may well have taken
his"doctrine of two worlds from Swedenborg direct" (Sewall 1900, p.25;see also pp.12-14, 24). Thus thereare good
grounds for regarding Swedenborg’s ‘spiritual’perspective as the mystical
equivalent of Kant’s transcendentalperspective in metaphysics. Such a
perspectival relationship is hinted at bySewall (1900): "Neither of the
two great system builders asks the supportof the other.... As Kant was
necessarily critical, this being the office [orPerspective] of the pure reason
itself, so was Swedenborg dogmatical, thisbeing the office [or Perspective] of
experience"(pp.22-3).
Sewallappends
to the 1900 translation of Dreams (pp.123-54) various extracts
fromSwedenborg’s writings, revealing that Swedenborg’s ideas oftenanticipate
(from his own mystical perspective), and therefore may haveinfluenced, many of
the key ideas Kant develops in his transcendentalphilosophy. The roots of
Kant’s transcendental idealism can be seen inSwedenborg’s spiritual idealism:
"spaces and times ... are in thespiritual world appearances";
"in heaven objects similar to thosewhich exist in our [empirical] world
... are appearances";"appearances are the first things out of which
the human mind forms itsunderstanding" (Sewall 1900, pp.124-6). The roots of Kant’s view of the
intelligiblesubstratum of nature are also evident: "nothing in nature
exists orsubsists, but from a spiritual origin, or by means of it";
"natureserves as a covering for that which is spiritual"; "there
exists aspiritual world, which is ... interior ... to the natural world,
therefore allthat belongs to the spiritual world is cause, and all that belongs
to thenatural world is effect"; "causes are things prior, and effects
arethings posterior; and things prior cannot be seen from things posterior,
butthings posterior can be seen from things prior. This is order" (Ibid,
pp.131-3).
Evenviews
similar to Kant’s "analogies of experience" in CPR are
developed bySwedenborg: "Material things ... are fixed, because, however
the states ofmen change, they continue permanent"; "The reason that
nothing innature exists but from a spiritual origin or principle is, that no
effect isproduced without a cause" (Ibid, pp.125, 132). The parallels extend beyond
thetheoretical to the practical and judicial standpoints as well: "the
willis the very nature itself or disposition of the man"; "heaven is
...within man".(Ibid, pp.138, 135).
Moreover, Kant’s Criticism of mystical visionaries as wronglytaking imagined
symbols to be real sensations cannot be charged againstSwedenborg, who warns:
"So long as man lives in the world he knows nothingof the opening of these
degrees within him, because he is then in the naturaldegree ...; and the
spiritual degree ... communicates with the natural degree,not
by continuity but by correspondences and communication by correspondencesis not
sensibly felt" (Ibid, p.135; see also p.141).
Ofcourse,
Kant’s use of such ideas often differs in important respects fromSwedenborg’s,
as when Kant argues for the importance of phenomenal causality asbeing
the only significant causality from the standpoint of knowledge.Nevertheless,
given the fact that before reading Swedenborg he did not writeabout such
matters, whereas afterwards such ‘Copernican’ ideasoccupied a central place in
his writings, it is hardly possible to doubt thatSwedenborg had a significant
influence on Kant’s mature thinking. I amnot claiming that Kant owes his
recognition of the importance of the Copernicanhypothesis to Swedenborg alone,
but only that his influence has been much neglected,and merits further
exploration.[32]
IfSwedenborg
did exercise an important influence on Kant, then why does Kant seemto give
Hume all the credit, for instance, in the oft-quoted passage from
theIntroduction to Prolegomena (see note 3)? Swedenborg was far from
being aphilosopher, so perhaps Kant did not feel constrained to acknowledge
hisinfluence — indeed, ‘felt embarrassed’ might bea more appropriate
expression, since Swedenborg’s reputation was hardlyrespectable among
Enlightenment philosophers. Kant’s request that hiswritings prior to 1770 not
be included in his collected minor writings (seenote 16) would therefore
reflect his desire to protect his reputation from tooclose an association with
the likes of Swedenborg. In any case, Kant’sclaim that the ideas he expresses
in Dreams predate his reading ofSwedenborg leaves open the
possibility that Swedenborg stimulated him to thinkthrough his own ideas more
carefully, and in the process to adopt some ofSwedenborg’s ideas, or at least
to use them as a stimulus to focus andclarify his own.
Doesthe
Prolegomena passage therefore represent a false‘confession’? By no means. But in order to understand that
passageproperly, and so to give an accurate answer to the question of the
relativeinfluence of Hume and Swedenborg on Kant, it will be necessary to
distinguishbetween four aspects of Kant’s development that are often conflated:
(1) Thegeneral
Critical method of finding the limits that definethe ‘middle way’
between unthinking acceptance of the status quo(dogmatism) and
unbelieving doubt as to the validity of the entire tradition(skepticism).
(2) Thegeneral
Copernican insight that the mostfundamental aspects of human knowledge
(the ones making it objective) havetheir source in the human subject as a
prioriforms, not vice versa. (That is, time, space, etc., are not absolute
realitiesrooted in the object, as philosophers had previously assumed.) This,
of course,was the seed that (when fertilized by the
Critical method) gave rise to theentire System of ‘transcendental
philosophy’.[33]
(3) Theparticular
application of (1) to itself (i.e.,reason’s Criticism
of reason itself).
(4) Theparticular
application of (2) to the problem of thenecessary connection between a
cause and its effect.
As stated above in §1, we can see (1) operatingin
varying degrees in almost all of Kant’s writings (see note 11).Indeed, his
lifelong acceptance of (1) is clearly the intellectual backgroundagainst which
alone his great philosophical achievements could have been made (andas such, is
the source of his genius). Although his ability to make conscioususe of this
method certainly developed gradually during his career, receivingits first
full-fledged application in Dreams, neitherSwedenborg
(the dogmatist) nor Hume (the skeptic) can be given the credit forthis. The
Critical method is not something Kant learned from these (orany other)
philosophers, but is rather the natural Tao through whichKant read, and
in reading, transformed, their ideas.[34] If anyone is to be thanked,it should
be his parents, and in particular, his mother.[35]
Kant’srecognition
of (4) as one of the crucial questions to be answered by his newphilosophical System, is, by contrast, clearly traceable to
Hume’sinfluence. In fact, his discussion of Hume’s impact on his development inProlegomena
(p.260[8]) undoubtedly refers primarily (if not solely) to this narrowsense of
"awakening": Kant is probably telling us nothing more thanthat his
"recollection" of Hume helped him recognize that causality cannotbe
treated as a purely intellectual principle (as he had done in Dissertation),
but must bejustified (if at all) in some other way (viz., as
atranscendental form of knowing, just as were space and time in Dissertation).
The fact thatKant uses the term ‘recollection’ indicates a fairly late date(probably 1772 [see note 4]) for this dramatic event.
For Kant is suggestingthat (4) came to him as a result of remembering
the skepticismof Hume ("the first spark of light") that had begun
influencing histhinking about ten years before. However, if Kant’s
famous"awakening" is only a dramatized account of his discovery of
(4),then such references to Hume do not answer the more fundamental question,
theanswer to which we have been seeking here: Where did Kant get the idea of
using(2) as the basic insight for solving all such philosophical
problems?
Kant’sdiscovery
of (2) came in several fairly well-defined steps, mostly from 1768 to1772.
Prior to 1768 there is little (if any) trace of such an idea. Between1768 and
1772 he applied the insight to intuitions but not to concepts. In 1772he
realized that concepts too must be regarded from this Copernican(Transcendental)
Perspective. As a result of this somewhat unsettling discovery(unsettling
because in early 1772 he believed he was within a few months of
completing CPR), he spent ninemore years (from 1772 to 1781)
working out in his mind the thoroughgoingimplications of this insight for his
entire philosophical System. It is plainenough to see how Hume’s ideas could
have caused the final (and crucial)change in the extent of Kant’s application
of (2) in 1772,because Hume employs some of his most powerful arguments to
support hisskepticism regarding the a priori basis of the idea of necessary
connection.Kant’s realization in 1772 of the full force of these arguments
awakenedhim to an awareness of the incomplete nature of his application of (2)
in Dissertation, and gave himthe idea of applying (2) to concepts as
well as to intuitions.
Butwhere
did (2) come from in the first place? It could not have come from Hume,inasmuch as nothing like it appears in Hume’s doctrines of
space and time(or anywhere else in Hume’s works). Hume’s explanation for
ourbelief in all such ‘objective facts’ is always to reduce them tologic and/or
an empirical kind of subjectivity (as he does in the finalparagraph of
his Inquiry); he never so much as hints at the possibility of anythird
way, such as is given by Kant’s theory of transcendental
subjectivity.There are, to my knowledge, only two likely explanations, both of
whichprobably worked together to awaken Kant to his Copernican insight
sometimebetween 1766 and 1768. The first is his reading of Swedenborg’s
writings,especially his massive work, Arcana Coelestia, which he readin
1766, just before writing Dreams (p.318[39]: Sewall 1900, p.14n); and
the second ishis reading of the Clarke-Leibniz Correspondence,[36] togetherwith
his consequent discovery of the antinomies of reason (see below). If
thisaccount of Kant’s development during these portentous years is correct,then Kant’s description of (4) as an awakening from dogmatic
slumber is asomewhat over-dramatized account, whose purpose is not to emphasize
a suddenbreak from lifelong dogmatism (cf. note 34), but only to explain how
Hume savedhim from settling for the half-baked form of (2) that he had
originallydistilled from the ideas of two thinkers whom he regarded as
dogmatists (Leibniz andSwedenborg). Thus, if we look at the overall
picture, we see that Hume’sinfluence has, in fact, been overrated; it fulfils
only one specific role inKant’s long process of development.
Thisinterpretation
of Kant’s development gives rise to two further questionsregarding Kant’s use
of his sleeping/dreaming/awakening metaphor. For heuses it
not only in relation to Hume’s influence, but also in many othercontexts.
In a letter to Garve (21 September 1798), for instance, he confidesthat his
discovery (c.1768) of "the antinomy of pure reason ... is whatfirst
aroused me from my dogmatic slumber and drove me to the critique ofreason
itself" (AA12:255[Zweig 1967, p.252]; see also note 7). How can this account of
Kant’s‘awakening’ be made compatible with his (better known) referencesto Hume?
Although interpreters have often struggled with this question, theanswer seems
obvious once we distinguish between the four aspects of
Kant’sdevelopment listed above. Kant’s comments must refer to differentexperiences
of awakening: the awakening by Hume refers to (4), while that for whichthe
antimony is responsible refers to (3). Accordingly, Kant says the
antinomyshowed him the need for a Critique of reason, whereas he says
Hume’sstimulus gave a "new direction" (Prolegomena p.260[8]) to hisspeculative research (thus implying he had
already begun working on thatCritique). The tendency to
regard these as referring to the same experiencearises only because he uses the
same metaphor to describe both developments.
Thesecond
question arises once we recognize the obviously close connection betweenKant’s
metaphor of being awoken from sleep and the metaphor of dreaming that
permeatesthe entirety of Dreams (even its title). Whether Kant’s
awakeningreally happened only in 1768 (via the antinomies) or only in 1772
(viaHume’s skepticism) — or even at both times — Kant’scomments would seem to
imply that Dreams itself dates from the period of"dogmatic
slumber" from which he only later awoke. Yet eventhose who do not
fully appreciate the Critical elements in Dreams agree that it
isnot the work of a sleeping dogmatist! So how could Kant’s metaphor applyto
anything that happened after he wrote this book? Without presuming to
give thefinal answer to this difficult question, I shall venture to offer a
plausiblesuggestion, based on the account of Kant’s development given above.
Criticismis the middle path between dogmatism and skepticism.
It is the tool Kantbelieved he could use to preserve the truth and value
of both methodsand yet do away with the errors into which each inevitably
falls. The Criticalmind will therefore always allow itself to be
"tempted", as it were,by the two extremes it
ultimately seeks to overcome; but in the process ofbecoming more and more
refined, it will appear at one moment to be moredogmatic and at another to be
more skeptical (just as we observed Kant’smind to be in the text of Dreams).
In other words, the Critical method does not doaway with skepticism and
dogmatism, so much as use them as opposing forcesto guide its insight further
along the spiral path towards the central point ofpure Critique. Now, in order
to stay healthy a human being needs both sleep andwaking; and in the same way,
we could develop Kant’s metaphor one stepfurther by saying the healthy
(Critical) philosopher needs regular doses ofboth dogmatism and skepticism.
Skepticism functions like an alarm clock toremind philosophers when it is time
to stop their dogmatic dreaming and returnto the normal waking life of Criticism.
The Critical philosopher will naturallyhave many experiences of this type, just
as a normal person is often surprisedto wake up in the middle of a dream, yet will dream again the next night. Thus,the confusion caused by Kant’s various references to his
awakening fromdogmatic slumbers may be best explained by regarding each as
equally legitimateand equally important milestones in his development.
Wehave
seen that Hume’s influence was never such as to convert Kant
toskepticism, but served only as "the first spark of light" (Prolegomena,
p.260[8]) tokindle his awareness of the need to
reflect on the rationality of his cherishedbeliefs. This limited view of
the influence of Hume on Kant comes out quiteclearly in almost all Kant’s
references to Hume or skepticism. In CPR, for example,Kant
again uses his favorite metaphor to describe the relation betweendogmatism,
skepticism, and Criticism: "At best [skepticism] is merely ameans of
awakening [reason] from its dogmatic dreams, and of inducing it toenter upon a
more careful examination of its own position" (p.785). Kant’s attempt in Dreams to
examinemysticism and metaphysics with a Critical eye should therefore be
regarded asresulting from one of his first major awakenings (perhaps largely as
a resultof his initial reading of Hume, probably in the early
1760s).Ironically, although he disagreed with the dogmatic use to
whichSwedenborg put his ideas, Kant seems to have recognized in them some
valuable hypotheses that could bepurified in the refining fire of Criticism.
The antinomies awoke him (in 1768)to the realization
that reason’s Critical method must be applied not onlyto objects of possible
knowledge (such as mystical experiences and metaphysicaltheories), but also to
reason itself. And just when he thought he was onthe verge of perfecting
this self-Criticism of reason (in 1772), Hume awoke himonce again to the
realization that his Copernican insight must be used to limitnot only intuition
but also the concepts arising out of human understanding. Wecan conclude,
therefore, that although Hume was instrumental in awakening Kantto the limits
of dogmatism, Swedenborg’s speculations wereresponsible in a more direct way
for the initial formation of his Copernicanhypothesis.
4. The Dream of a System of Critical Philosophy
Aclear
understanding of the influence of Swedenborg on Kant, and of the functionof Dreams
as a Critical prolegomenon to Kant’s mature System of transcendental
Critique, makesit not so surprising to hear Sewall (1900) say mystics
"from Jung-Stillingto Du Prel" have always "claimed Kant as
being of their number"(pp.16-17, 32). Indeed, Du Prel (1885, Vol 2,
pp.195-8, 243, 290) stressesKant’s positive attitude towards Swedenborg, and
argues that in Dreams "Kant ...declared Mysticism possible,
supposing man to be ‘a member at once of thevisible and of the invisible
world’" (p.302).[37] He even suggeststhat "Kant would confess to-day
[i.e., in the 1880s] that hundreds of suchfacts [based on various types of
parapsychological experience] are proved"(p.198). This is probably going
too far, but so is Vaihinger’s conclusionthat "Kant’s world of experience
... excludes all invasion of theregular system of nature by uncontrollable
‘spirits’; and the wholesystem of modern mysticism, so far as he holds fast to
his fundamentalprinciples, Kant is ‘bound to forcibly reject’" (Sewall
1900,p.19). Kant is forced to reject mysticism only as a componentof his
theoretical system (i.e., CPR); the other systems neverthelessremain
open to nontheoretical interpretations of mystical experiences. Sewallreflects
Kant’s purposes more accurately when he writes:
The
great mission ofKant was to establish ... [that reason] can neither create a knowledge of thespiritual world, nor can it deny the
possibility of such a world. It can affirmindeed the rationality of such a
conception, but the realityof it does not come within its domain as pure
reason.(pp.20-1)
AsVaihinger
himself admits elsewhere, Kant’s apparent rejection ofmysticism (and so also,
parapsychology) therefore "refers only to thepractices (of spiritism), and
to the Mysticism of the Feelings; it does notapply to the rational
belief of Kant in the ‘corpus mysticum of theintelligible
world.’"(Sewall 1900, p.25).[38]
Kanttherefore
has two distinct, though closely related, purposes in Dreams. The first
is toreject unCritical (speculative or fanatical) forms of mysticism, not in
orderto overthrow all mysticism, but in order to replace it with a refined, Critical
version,directed towards our experience of this world and our reflection
on it fromvarious perspectives. This perspectival element in Kant’s mysticism
ishinted at by Vaihinger when he says Kant believes:
The
other world is ...not another place, but only another view of even this
world.... [It] is not aworld of other things, but of the same things seen
differently by us.... Butthe wildly fermenting must of the Swedenborgian
Mysticism becomes with Kantclarified and settled into the noble, mild, and yet
strong wine of criticism.(Sewall 1900, pp.15,18)
Unfortunately, the general mystical thrust ofKant’s
System of Perspectives has been grossly neglected by almost allEnglish-speaking
Kant-scholars.[39] In Part Four of KCR (see note 13) Ihave attempted to
set right this neglect by examining the extent to whichKant’s Critique of
mysticism in Dreams paves the wayfor a full-blooded ‘Critical
mysticism’.
Kant’ssecond
purpose in clearing from the path of metaphysics the obstructionscreated by the
speculative claims of mystical experiences is to prepare the wayfor his own
attempt to provide a metaphysical System that could do formetaphysics what Dreams
does for mystical visions and all forms ofparapsychological experience.[40] For
the Critical dream envisaged in Dreams was to serve asa seed planted in
his reason, which eventually matured into the tree ofCritical philosophy; and
only when this tree finally bears fruit does themystical seed that gave birth
to the System appear once again (i.e., in OpusPostumum). Accordingly,
Kant’s Critical labors can be regarded as anattempt to build a rational System
that preserves the truemystical dream, thus putting mysticism and
parapsychology in their true place,at the mysterious (yet nonetheless real)
centre of metaphysicsand physics, respectively. In this sense, at least,
Kant would agree with DuPrel (1885) when he says: "It is ... dream, not
waking, which is the doorof metaphysic, so far as the latter deals with
man" (Vol 1, p.70).
REFERENCES
Beck,L. W. (Trans.) (1950). Revised version of P. Carus'
translation of I. Kant's(1783) Prolegomena to Any
Future Metaphysics. New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Co., Inc.
Beck,L. W. (Trans.) (1956). I. Kant’s (1788) Critique of
Practical Reason. Indianapolis: The Bobbs-Merrill Co., Inc
Beck,L. W. (1969). EarlyGerman Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.:
HarvardUniversity Press.
Beck.L. W. (1987). Review of G.Gawlick & L.
Kreimendahl's Hume in der deutschen Aufklärung. In
Eighteenth-Century Studies, 20, 405-8.
Beiser,F. C. (1992). Kant’s intellectual development:
1746-1781. In Paul Guyer (Ed.) The CambridgeCompanion to Kant. Cambridge:
Cambridge UniversityPress.
Broad,C. D. (1953). Religion, Philosophy and
Psychical Research. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.
Cassirer,E. (1921, 1918). Kants Leben und Lehre2. Translated byJ. Haden (1981) as Kant’s
Life and Thought. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Copleston,F. C. (1960). A
History ofPhilosophy, vol. VI, Wolff to Kant. London:Burns
and Oates Ltd.
Dell’Oro,R. O. M. (1994).
From Existenceto the Ideal: Continuity and Development in Kant’s
Theology. New York: Peter Lang.
DuPrel,
C. (1885). DiePhilosophie der
Mystik. Translated byC. C. Massey (1889) as The
Philosophy of Mysticism, 2 vols. London: George Redway; reprinted in 1976
(NewYork: Arno Press).
Fang,J. (1967). Kant-Interpretationen. Münster: Verlag Regensberg.
Gerding,J. L. F. (1994). Was Kant a sceptic? In Proceedings of
the ParapsychologicalAssociation’s 37th Annual Convention.Utrecht: The
Parapsychological Association.
Gulick,W. B. (1994). The creativity of the intellect: From
ontology to meaning. Thetransmutation of the sensible and
intelligible worlds in Kant’s Criticalthought’, Ultimate Reality and
Meaning, 17, 99-108.
Gulyga,A. (1985). Kant. Translatedby M. Despalatovic (1987) as Immanuel
Kant: His Life and Thought. Boston: Birkhäuser.
Jonsson,I. (1967). ‘Swedenborg, Emanuel’, in P.
Edwards (Ed.) TheEncyclopedia of Philosophy. London:
CollierMacmillan Publishers. Vol 8.
Kant,I. (1762-1795). Vorlesungenüber Metaphysik. In Preußischen Akademie
derWissenschaften (Eds), Kants gesammelte Schriften, Akadamie
Ausgabe.29 vols. AA28.1; AA28.2,1; AA29. Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter.
Kant,I. (1764a). Beobachtungen über das Gefühl
des Schönen undErhabenen. In Preußischen Akademie derWissenschaften
(Eds), Kants gesammelte Schriften, Akadamie Ausgabe.29 vols.
AA2:205-56. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Kant,I. (1764b). Versuchüber die Krankheiten des
Kopfes. In Preußischen Akademie
derWissenschaften (Eds), Kants gesammelte Schriften, Akadamie
Ausgabe.AA2:257-271. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter
Kant,I.(1766). Träume eines Geistersehers, erläutert durch
Träumeder Metaphysik. In Preußischen Akademie derWissenschaften (Eds), Kants gesammelte Schriften, Akadamie
Ausgabe.29 vols. AA2:315-73 = CE1: 303-59. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Kant,I. (1770). De mundi sensibilis atque intelligibilis
forma et principiis. In
Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (Eds), Kantsgesammelte Schriften,
Akadamie Ausgabe. 29 vols. AA2:385-419 = CE1:375-416; Berlin:
Walter deGruyter.
Kant,I. (1783). Prolegomenazu einer jeden künftigen
Metaphysik die als Wissenschaft wird auftretenkönnen. In Preußischen Akademie
derWissenschaften (Eds), Kants gesammelte
Schriften, Akadamie Ausgabe.29 vols. AA4:253-383 (cf. CE3) Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter.
Kant,I. (1787/1781). Kritik der reinen Vernunft,2 InPreußischen
Akademie der Wissenschaften (Eds), Kants gesammelteSchriften, Akadamie
Ausgabe. 29 vols. AA3 (passim)(1787 version);
AA4:1-252 (1781version). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Kant,I. (1788). Kritik der praktischen Vernunft.In
Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (Eds), Kants
gesammelteSchriften, Akadamie Ausgabe. 29 vols. AA5:1-163 = CE4:137-271.
Berlin: Walter deGruyter.
Kant,I. (1790). Kritik derUrtheilskraft. In Preußischen Akademie
derWissenschaften (Eds), Kants gesammelte Schriften, Akadamie
Ausgabe.29 vols., AA5:165-485 (cf. CE5). Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter.
Kant,I. (1798). Der Streit der Facultäten.AA7:1-116.
Berlin: Walter de Gruyter
Kerferd,G. B. and Walford, D. E. (Trans.) (1968). I. Kant's (1770) On
the Form andPrinciples of the Sensible and Intelligible World in G. B.
Kerferd and D. E. Walford (Eds) SelectedPre-Critical Writings and
Correspondence with Beck. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Klinke,W. (1949). Kant für Jedermann.
Translated by M.Bullock (1952) as Kant For Everyman. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Kuehn,M. (1983). Kant’s Conception of 'Hume’s Problem', Journal of the History of Philosophy,21,
175-193.
Laywine,A. (1993). Kant’s
EarlyMetaphysics and the Origins of the Critical Philosophy. Atascadero, Ca.: Ridgeview Publishing Company.
Manolesco,J.
(1969) ‘Introduction’, in his translation of I. Kant's Dreams of a
Spirit Seer Illustrated by Dreams of Metaphysics. New York: Vantage Press.
McCarthy,V. A. (1982). Christus as Chrestus in Rousseau and Kant, Kant-Studien,
73,
191-207.
Meredith,J. C. (Trans.) (1952). I. Kant’s[(1790)]
Critique of Judgement.Oxford: The Clarendon Press (reprinted from his
1911 and 1928 translations ofthe two Parts).
Palmquist,S. (1987). A Complete Index to Kemp Smith’s Translation
ofKant’s Critique of Pure Reason.Oxford and Hong Kong: distributed
privately. Also available as e-text at www.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp/indx/toc.html
(correct March 2001).
Palmquist,S. (1993). Kant’s System of Perspectives. Lanham,
MD: University Press of America.
Palmquist,S. (2000). Kant’s Critical Religion.Aldershot,
England: Ashgate Publishing Limited.
Paulsen,F. (1898). Immanuel Kant: Sein Leben und seine Lehre.
Translated by J. E. Creighton and A. Lefèbvre(1902) as
Immanuel Kant: His Life and Doctrine. New York: Fredrick Unger
Publishing Co.
PreußischenAkademie
der Wissenschaften (Eds) (1902-present). Kants
gesammelteSchriften, Akadamie Ausgabe. 29 vols. Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter.
Rabel,G. (Ed.) (1963). Kant. Oxford: TheClarendon Press.
Richardson,J. (Trans., anon.)(1799). I. Kant’s (1764) Observations
on the Feelingof the Beautiful and the Sublime in(1798-9) Essays and
Treatises on Moral, Political, Religious and VariousPhilosophical Subjects,
2 vols. London:William Richardson; reprinted. G. Micheli (1993), Bristol:
Thoemmes Press.
Sewall,F. (Ed.) (1900).
I. Kant's Dreamsof a Spirit Seer Illustrated by Dreams of Metaphysics,
trans. E. F. Goerwitz. London: Swan
Sonnenschein & Co.
Smith,N. K. (Trans.) (1929). I. Kant's[(1787/1781)] Critique of Pure
Reason. London: Macmillan &
Co. Ltd.
Ütz,G. F. (1992). Swedenborgsverborgene
Wirkung auf Kant. Translated byJ. D. Odhner and K.
Nemitz (1993-1995) as Swedenborg’s HiddenInfluence on Kant, in a series
of installmentspublished in The New Philosophy, 96-98:
vols. 96(1993),
171-225, 277-307; 97(1994), 347-96, 461-98; 98
(1995), 99-108;etc
Wallace,W. (1901). Kant. London:William
Blackwood and Sons.
Ward,K. (1972). The Development of Kant’s View of Ethics.
Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Werkmeister,W. H. (1980). Kant: The Architectonic and Development of
His Philosophy. London: Open Court Press.
Wolff,R. P. (1960). Kant’s Debt to Hume Via Beattie Journal of the History
of Ideas, 21, 117-23.
Zweig,A. (1967). Kant:
PhilosophicalCorrespondence 1759-99. Chicago: TheUniversity of Chicago
Press.
FOOTNOTES
1.Kant (1776); Sewall (1900), p.373 (121). Sewall (1990)
will hereafter be referred to as Dreamsin the text. References to Kant’s
writings, as in Kant (1776), will beidentified by the volume and page numbers
in the standard, PreußischenAkademie der Wissenschaften (Eds.) (1902-present)
edition and the equivalentvolume and page numbers in the new Cambridge Edition
of Kant’s Works inEnglish — abbreviated ‘AA’ and ‘CE’,respectively. The
translation quoted, if different from the CE translation, isthen identified,
along with the abbreviation that will be used in all furtherreferences to that
book. References to Kant’s writings will normally beidentified by these
abbreviations and included in the main text, citing theGerman page number(s);
the English page number(s) follow(s) in square bracketsin cases where the
German pagination is not included in the English textquoted.
2. Kant (1770); Kerferd & Walford(1968). This book was Kant’s inaugural dissertation
for his professorialpost at the University of Königsberg, so I shall refer to
it hereafter as Dissertation.
3.The latter is based on Kant's [1783] own account of the
matter: "I openlyconfess my recollection of David Hume was the very thing
which many years agofirst interrupted my dogmatic slumber and gave my
investigations in the fieldof speculative philosophy a quite new
direction". (p.260, [Beck (1950),p.8]). Beck (1950) will hereafterbe referred to
as Prolegomena in the text.
4.In a note to his translation of ProlegomenaLewis
White Beck (1950) suggests that "Kant had probably read Hume before1760,
but only much later (1772?) did he begin to follow 'a
new direction' underHume’s influence" ([p.8n]). Beck (1969) defends his
position in EarlyGerman Philosophy; see also Wolff (1960). In Dissertationand
as late as 1772, in a letter to Marcus Herz, Kant shows no awareness thatHume’s
skepticism challenges his own conception of causality as anintellectual
principle. The supposed reason is that Kant was familiar only withHume’s Enquiry
(1748), with its relatively modestskepticism, until he read Beattie’s Essay
on the Nature andImmutability of Truth (1772), which contains translations
of long passagesfrom the more radically skeptical text of Hume’s Treatise(1738).
Beck (1987) confirms his acceptance of this explanation despite morerecent
conjectures that Kant’s friend, Hamann, who translated part of theTreatise
in 1771, may have shown his translation to Kant asearly as 1768.
Paulsen(1898) affirms that Kant "did not receive the
impetus to his work [i.e., Dreams]from the English writers, and especially
from Hume’s epistemologicalinvestigations", (pp.87-8). The influence of
Hume, he argues, came mainlyin the early 1770s "as furnishing an incentive
to turn towards hisoriginal [i.e., Kant’s own unique] position" (pp.93-4),
and to alesser extent, just prior to the writing of Dissertationin 1770
(pp.97-9). This supports the view I shall defend in §3, thatHume’s
"awakening" refers primarily to the change from Dissertationto
the first Critique.
Boththese
suggestions account only for Kant’s recognition of the needfor a more
adequate defense of the philosophical principle of causality. Theysay nothing
positive about the source of what I take to be the two mostfundamental aspects
of Kant’s mature philosophical System: his Criticalmethod and his ‘Copernican’
assumption. Moreover, they also fail toaccount for the unique (Humean?)
character of Dreams.In §3, I shall propose an alternative explanation of
Kant’sdevelopment, which makes up for these and other inadequacies of the
traditionalview.
5.This conjecture is supported not only by Kant’s age (early
40s), but alsoby his cynical dissatisfaction with the status quo. Manolesco
(1969) treats"Kant’s sudden hatred for speculative metaphysics" as
"adeep psychological change due to unrequited love, not by metaphysics but
bySwedenborg himself" (pp.14-15)for not replying to Kant’s queries. Moreover, Kant was
involved in failedlove affairs with at least two women at around this time (see
e.g., Klinke1949, pp.39-41; Wallace 1901, pp.44-5; and especially, Gulyga 1985,
pp.54-5.)
6.Kant (1787/1781), AA3:passim(second edition) and
AA4:1-252 (passages unique to first edition) = CE2:passim(both
editions); Smith, (1929), pp.xvi-xviii.
Smith (1929) will hereafter be referred to as CPR (=Critique
of Pure Reason) in the text. References are to the1787 edition, unless the
page number is preceded by ‘A’.
7.The emphasized words indicate that Kant was still mindful
of his earlier workin Dreams which, as will become apparent in this
essay, adoptsthe same point of view expressed in this quotation. In fact, Kant
uses termsreferring to this sleeping/dreaming/ awakening metaphor 27 times in CPR(see
Palmquist 1987, pp.34,109, 347), most of which echo quite clearly theattitudes
adopted in Dreams. The most significantreferences are CPR pp. Ap.xiii,
503, 519-21,785, 792 (but see also pp. Ap.xin, xxxvi, 1, A112, 217, 247, 278,
A376-7, A380,A390, 434, 452, 479, 652, 808). Such
texts should not, however, be taken asevidence that Kant was completely against
all mysticism. Rather, they restatethe same problem posed in Dreams—viz.,
howone’s "cherished dreams" canbe preserved, if not by dogma
and/or magic. Kant’s solutionto this crucial problem is fully examined
in Part Four of Palmquist(2000). Palmquist (2000) willhereafter be referred
to as KCR (= Kant's CriticalReligion) in the text. The present
essay, incidentally, is arevised version of KCR, Chapter II.
8
These twomodes of representation are similar, though not identical, to the
distinction Imake between ‘immediate experience’ and ‘reflectiveknowledge’ in
Palmquist (1993), IV.1. Palmquist
(1993) will hereafter be referred to as KSP(= Kant’s
System of Perspectives) in the text. Seealso KCR, III.2. References
to these two books cite thechapter and section (or note) numbers; this renders
them easier to locate usingthe e-text versions available on my web site,
currently (March 2001) located atwww.hkbu.edu.hk/~ppp
9.See e.g., CPR 352,A395. Palmquist (1987, p.86)
lists 168 occurrencesof these three words in CPR.
10.Indeed, as I argued throughout KSP, the making of
suchperspectival distinctions is the key task of the Critical philosopher
(seeespecially KSP II.1).
11.In the earlier works, of course, the traces are evident
retrospectively eventhough Kant himself would not yet have been conscious of
the significance ofthe naturally Critical tendencies of his way of thinking. In
fact, becomingconscious of what was already thereseems to be one
of the implications of his much-used metaphor ofsleeping/dreaming/awakening
(see note 7). Otherwise a metaphor such as‘coming alive’ or ‘giving birth’
would have been moreappropriate.
12.Swedenborg (1688-1772) was not only the founder of
crystallography, but alsomade significant advances in a wide range of
scientific, technological, andeconomic fields. For an account of such
accomplishments, see the openingsection of Ütz (1992); see also Laywine (1993,
pp.57-8).
13.Kant’s interest in the spirit world is almost always
neglected, if notoutright denied, by Kant scholars nowadays. Yet throughout his
life herepeatedly affirmed a belief in its reality. Even in CPRhe uses
‘spirit’ and its cognates 16 times (see Palmquist 1987,p.353), affirming his
commitment to a surprisingly Platonic view of theeternality of the human
spirit: "we can propound a transcendentalhypothesis, namely, that all life
is, strictly speaking, intelligible only, isnot subject to changes of time, and
neither begins in birth nor ends in death;that this life is an appearance only,
that is, a sensible representation of thepurely spiritual life, and that the
whole sensible world is a mere picturewhich in our present mode of knowledge
hovers before us, and like a dream hasin itself no objective reality; that if
we could intuit ourselves and things asthey are, we should see ourselves
in a world of spiritualbeings, our sole and true community with which has not
begun through birth andwill not cease through bodily death — both birth and
death being mereappearances." (CPR, pp.807-8)
14.The
subtle difference between this and the usual interpretation can beillustrated
by quoting Werkmeister’s (1980) claim that in DreamsKant concludes
"that metaphysics ought to abandon its dogmaticspeculations about God, the
life hereafter, and similar topics" (p.64).This is correct, provided
we understand (asWerkmeister himself hints elsewhere (cf. note 16) that
abandoning dogmaticspeculation does not entail altogether abandoning
belief in God,etc., as is assumed by those who regard Dreamsas the work
of an outright skeptic. Kant abandons speculation not in order toswing over to
the skepticism of unbelief, but in order to make room for aCritical reformation
of his beliefs.
15.On the dating of this letter, see: Sewall (1900), p.160;
Broad (1953),pp.117-8; and Rabel (1963), p.74.
16.Laywine (1993), pp.60-61, gives a good summary of the first
three visionsSwedenborg made public, each mentioned in Kant’s letters.
Kant’stendency
in Dreams to ridicule views towards which he was in factsympathetic may
be what led him to suggest this book be excluded from hiscollected minor
writings (see Sewall 1900, p.x; Manolesco 1969, p.7). Paulsen(1898,
p.84) admits that the "spiritology" in Dreams"is not
intended [by Kant] to be entirely without seriousness",inasmuch as it
foreshadows the important ‘two worlds’ doctrinelater propounded in CPR.
Later he relates this to"Kant’s Platonism", already evident in Dreams "an
ethical and religious view ofthe world on the basis of objective idealism"
(p.310). Mendelssohncaptures the strangeness of Kant’s mood in Dreamswhen
he writes in a book review: "The jesting profundity with which thislittle
work has been written leaves the reader at times in doubt as to whetherMr. Kant
intended to make metaphysics ridiculous or spiritism (Geisterseherei)plausible" (Werkmeister 1980, p.43). The answer, as we
shall see, is bothand neither: making unCritical approaches to
both issues lookridiculous prepares the way for the Critical method to reveal
the plausibilityof both, when viewed Critically. For Dreamsadopts
an entirely Critical method, and so first poses the problem (thoughsomewhat
obscurely) that is to be solved by Kant’s mature philosophicalSystem. That Kant
is intentionally using Swedenborg’s visions as a testcase for the
application of his well-formed Criticalmethod, before launching into its
application to all of metaphysics, isindicated in his 1766 letter to
Mendelssohn (in Manolesco 1969, pp.154-9),where he calls attention to the
"important conclusions which are meant todetermine in a strict manner the methodologyof
[the new metaphysics]", and then invites Mendelssohnto use this new
(Critical) method "to draw up a new master plan for thisscience"
(Manolesco 1969, pp.156-7, emphasis added). See also Laywine(1993,
pp.72-100) and Werkmeister (1980, pp.44,84) for similar views of theprefiguring
role of Dreams.
Werkmeister(1980) quotes Borowski’s biography of Kant as
saying "the attentivereader found already here [in Dreams] the
seeds of the Critiqueof Pure Reason and of that which Kant gave us
later."Unfortunately, he gives no details as to just which aspects of Dreamsconstitute
these "seeds". After using the same metaphor (Dreams"contains
... many of the seeds of Kant’s Critical Philosophy"[Manolesco 1969,
p.13]), Manolesco lists some examples: Kant’s"theory of spirits is almost
an exact replica, expressed in philosophicallanguage, of Swedenborg’s own
thesis ... Swedenborgian doctrines ...provided him with fundamental
metaphysical starting points for his later viewson the soul, on the dualism of
mind and matter, on his conception of noumenaand phenomena, on inner sense and
its connection with the unity ofapperception." (pp.17-18)
17.McCarthy (1982) makes the interesting suggestion thatKant’s
mature philosophy replaces ‘Christus’ (Latin for‘anointed’) with ‘Crestus’
(Latin for‘useful’). If so, Kant’s third point can be regarded as aforetaste of
what is to come. We must keep in mind, however, that‘useful’ for Kant means
‘useful in bringing aboutgoodness’; it is not a sudden leaning towards
utilitarianism (cf. Kant[1762-1795, AA28.1, AA28.2,1, and AA29 = CE10:passim).McCarthy
(1982) shows his implicit awareness of the moral aspect of the Kantian‘useful’
when he says his (like Kant’s) concern is with"the role of Jesus the
(morally) ‘Useful’" (p.192). WhatMcCarthy seems to ignore is that the
‘Crestus’ need not excludethe ‘Cristus’; as I argue in Part Three of KCR,both
can (and should) work together as complements.
18.Kant notes in Dreams that this "prevalent
opinionwhich assigns to the soul its seat in the brain, seems to originate
mainly inthe fact, that we feel distinctly how, in deep meditation, the nerves
of thebrain are taxed. But if this conclusion is right it would prove also
otherabodes of the soul. In anxiety or joy the sensation seems to have its seat
inthe heart. Many affections, yea most of them,
manifest themselves most stronglyin the diaphragm. Pity moves the intestines,
and other instincts manifest theirorigin in other organs" (p.325n[50n]).
Here we see a good example of Kant’s awareness of andconcern for the
condition of his own body. Unfortunately, interpreters tend toexcuse this
concern as stemming merely from his eccentric ideas about how hecould maintain
his own health through sheer will power and self-determination(see e.g., Kant
[1764, AA2:257-71]; Kant [1798, Part III, AA7:1-116 =CE6:237-327]). Yet it
seems also to reveal the importance he placed onfostering a meditative
awareness of his immediate experience:philosophy
for Kant is ultimately not an abstract function of the mind orbrain, but a discipline
in which the whole bodyparticipates as well.
19.
See alsoAA28:146-7 and Laywine (1993, pp.52,159).
Laywine makes a good case for viewingsoul-body interaction as the chief
philosophical concern around which most ofKant’s pre-Copernican writings
revolved. She argues that, prior to Dreams,Kant was (at least
implicitly) committed to a theory of "physicalinflux", whereby the
soul has quasi-material characteristics, such asimpenetrability, and that in
the process of grappling with Swedenborg’svulgar version of the same view, Kant
recognized the need to give it up. Isummarize and assess her interpretation in
Appendix II.2 of KCR.
20."The
relation [of these ‘incorporealsubstances’] by means of things corporeal is
consequently to be regardedas accidental" (Dreams p.330[56-7]). Since an"undoubted characteristic of
life" is "free movement"(including growth), Kant suggests that
both plants and animals may also have animmaterial nature (p.330[57]).
In order to show the close connection betweenplants and animals Kant mentions
Boerhave’s view: "The animal is aplant which has its roots in the stomach
(inside)." He then
opines the converseis also true: "The plant is an animal which has its
stomach in the root(outside)." But he warns that
"such conjectures ... have the ridiculeof fashion against them, as being
dusty antiquated fancies"; "theappeal to immaterial principles is a
subterfuge of bad philosophy", so hewill "not ... use any of these
considerations as evidence"(p.331[58]).
21. Kant conjectures that the
spiritualconceptions that arise in the deepest, dreamless sleep "may be
clearer andbroader than even the clearest in the waking state. This is to be
expected ofsuch an active being as the soul when the external senses are so
completely atrest. For man, at such times is not sensible of his body."
When dreaming,by contrast, a person "perceives to
a certain degree clearly, and weavesthe actions of his spirit into the
impressions of the external senses."Unfortunately, Kant does not
acknowledge the importance of this connectivefunction of dreams, so instead of
regarding them as revealing profound symbolsof spiritual conceptions (as Jung,
using Kant as his philosophical springboard,has since suggested [see Appendix
II.1 of my KCR]),he ridicules them as being "only wild and absurd
chimeras" [Dreams338n(68n)]. Du Prel (1885) develops an elaborate
theory of ‘somnambulism’(including hypnotism) based
explicitly on Kant’s philosophy [see e.g., DuPrel 1885, vol. 1, pp.xxvi, 5-7,
62, 71, etc.]. He also agrees with Kant onmany specific points [see e.g., Du
Prel 1885, pp.57-8]. For example he says:"With the deepening of sleep must
diminish the confusion of thedream." (Ibid.,
p.44). In arguing for "the scientificimportance of dream", he claims
this clarity can be explained best byassuming that in deepest sleep the center
of control changes from the brain(the focus of consciousness) to the solar
plexus (the focus of theunconscious), and that the more control exercised by
the latter, the moresignificant the dream will be (Ibid., pp.27-44, 68-9)
22. The concluding paragraph of
ChapterThree, containing these comments, also includes some harsh ridicule of
thosewho adopt the perspective of Chapter Two. He suggests, for instance,
thatalthough visionaries are not necessarily insane, "insanity [is] a
likelyconsequence of such communion.... Therefore, I do not at all blame the
reader,if, instead of regarding the spirit-seers as half-dwellers in another
world[the view Kant himself seems to prefer], he, without further
ceremony,dispatches them as candidates for the hospital" (p.348[83]). No
doubt thisis one of the embarrassing remarks in Dreamsthat led Kant to
suggest in later life that it be excluded from his collectedminor works (see
Sewall 1900, p.x).
23.Cf. my book KSP, IX.4 (p.307) and note II.12. For an
explanation ofKant’s ‘judicial’ standpoint (that of the third Critique),see notes I.13 and I.17 of KCR.
24. This position has an obvious
affinitywith the doctrines of the positive and negative noumenon developed in CPR[see my book, KSP, VI.3].
25. Thus, Kant notes(p.350n[87-8n])
that our speculative ignorance "does not at all invalidatethe confidence
that the conceptions thence evolved [i.e., from hope] areright." For
example, the "inner perception" that death is"only a
transformation" leads "to that point to which reasonitself would lead
us if it were more enlightened, and of a greater scope."Kant is saying our
immediate experience can provide existential certainty for aposition that
cannot be proved theoretically. This existential certainty isgrounded in what
Kant calls "rational faith" [see KCR,note
IV.15].
26. For a fuller explanation of
thisfundamental distinction between immediate experience (which, as such,
producesno knowledge) and the various reflective forms of experience (which do
produceknowledge), see my book, KSP, IV.1,and
the summary of that section given in the first sequel, KCR,III.2.
27.This emphasis on the useful in Dreams may have
arisen to someextent out of Kant’s Wolffian education. For Wolff himself
stressed theimportance of "the useful" (see e.g., Copleston 1960,
p.112). Kantdid not abandon this emphasis in his mature writings, but rather
transformed itinto the hypothetical perspective in his theoretical system
(i.e., the first Critique)and into the
practical standpoint of his overall philosophical System.
Inthe
final chapter of Dreams the same strategy isemployed to address the
issue of the possibility of a spiritual influence onthe body: such influences
are possible but cannot be proved because they arenot governed by corporeal
laws. This is directly parallel to Kant’smature attitude towards "noumenal
causality", which cannot beregarded as knowable because it does not fall
under the a prioriprinciples of the
possibility of experience.
28.Indeed, Kant even uses the metaphor of awakening in the
skeptical chapter of Dreams(p.342[74], quoted above, in §2), thus
indicating that in 1766 he wasalready thinking of skepticism as a useful tool
for stimulating philosophers toreconsider their dogmatism. This fact, as we
shall see later in this section,raises serious questions about the traditional
view that Kant’s"awakening" by Hume did not happen until 1768, or
perhaps even 1772(see note 4).
29.Moreover, Kant uses the same metaphor in CPR 795,where
he refers to "the assay-balance of criticism" (see also CPR pp.617,811).And
he uses the corresponding metaphor of "weighing" two
opposingarguments in CPR A388-9,615,617,665,778, as well as in Kritik
der praktischenVernunft, (see Beck 1956, p.76).
30.As early as 1764 Kant recognized a special relationship
between metaphysics,moral philosophy, and philosophy of religion (see Kant
1764; Richardson 1799,vol.2, p.246n[63n]). In June of 1771 Kant affirmed in a
letter to Marcus Herzthat his project would have to address the topics of
metaphysics, morality, andaesthetics. And his letter
to Herz in February 1772 shows he already conceivedof his task as including
work on "the principles of feeling, taste, andpower of judgement" in
addition to its theoretical and moral aspects(AA10:124;
translated in Zweig 1967, p.71). Although he apparently had not yetdecided to
devote a separate Critique to each subject, he hadalready thought
of the title ‘Critique of Pure Reason’ (AA10.126[bid.,p.73]).
For a concise summary of the importance of these two letters,
seeCopleston 1960, pp.203-7.
31.I examine the details of the architectonic structure of
Kant’s System in KSP,III.3-4. A brief summary of those sections is given
inmy book, KCR, III.1; see also Appendix III.1.
32.Laywine (1993) makes significant headway in this direction
(see also note 19),though she reaches some rather questionable conclusions. For
a detaileddiscussion of her interpretation, see Appendix II.2 of my book KCR.
33.This distinction between Kant’s Critical method and the transcendentalorientation
of his philosophy is often ignored by Kant-scholars, who tend toconflate the
terms by talking about Kant’s "transcendentalmethod" – a phrase Kant
himself never uses. This type ofinterpretive error lies behind Cassirer’s
(1921, 1918) claim that in CPR"Kant is presenting a completely
novel type of thinking,one in opposition to his own past and to the
philosophy of the Age ofEnlightenment" (p.141). This notion of a complete
"opposition"between Kant’s past (wherein he is portrayed as being unknowingly
dupedby his dogmatic upbringing) and his Critical outlook (which is supposed to
havesprung as suddenly as the ringing of an alarm clock from his reading of
Hume)typifies the mythical account of Kant’s development against which I
amarguing in this essay. In CPR Kant is not negatinghis past, but
pressing it to its proper limit; he is separating the wheat fromthe chaff of
his own background and of his Age (see e.g., CPR Ap.xin)by bringing into full view the Critical method that had
characterized his wayof thinking from the start of his career.
Oneexception
to the above is J. Fang (1967), who calls attention to the mistake ofregarding
Kant’s method as transcendental(pp.112-3). He
also recognizes the importance of distinguishing between theCritical method and
the transcendental character of Kant’s maturephilosophy: the "critical
method" is already "partiallyrevealed" (i.e., applied) in
1770, but "concerns itself with‘limits’ alone ... and not yet with
‘sources’", as it does in its
transcendentalapplication (Fang 1967, pp.118-9). With intimations of Einstein,
he thensuggests that "the special critical method of1768-69, viz.,
‘to determine the validity and bounds of intuitiveprinciples’, had to be
generalized, and when it was finally‘broadened’, the general critical
method was todiscover and justify ... the sources, the extent, and the limits
of the humanfaculty of knowledge or metaphysic in general — the main task of
the Critique."(p.121) Unfortunately, Fang
does not work out in any detail the significance ofthis distinction (which
relates more to Kant’s gradual application of hisCopernican insight than to the
Critical method as such), nor does he mention Dreamsas relevant to the
development of Kant’s Critical method.
34.This
implies that the traditional view of Dreamsas a temporary excursion into
Humean skepticism [see §1, above] isentirely unjustified, based as it is on a
shallow reading of the text and aneglect of the ubiquity of the Critical method
in Kant’s writings.Hume’s influence on Kant in the early 1760s was only one of
manyinfluencing factors acting together as grist for the Critical
mill.Interestingly, neither Hume nor Swedenborg is included in
Werkmeister’sdescription of "the complexus of ideas which is the basis for
all furtherdevelopment of Kant’s philosophy" [Werkmeister 1980, p.15].
35.Kant’s biographers consistently report the strong influence
he felt hismother had on his general personal and intellectual development. I
discuss herinfluence further in KCR, X.4.
36.In fact, the influence of Swedenborg is quite compatible
with the influence ofLeibniz. For Swedenborg himself
studied Descartes, Leibniz, and Wolff, much asKant did in his early years (see
Jonsson 1967, p.47). (In §335.7 and§696 of The True Christian Religion
Swedenborg evendescribes his visions of Aristotle, Descartes and Leibniz,
together with nineof their followers, among whom was Wolff.) Thus, Kant’s
reading ofSwedenborg may well have worked together with his readingof
the Clarke-Leibniz Correspondence to point him towardsthe Copernican
hypothesis.
37.The term ‘mysticism’ in this quote (as elsewhere in this
essay)might well be replaced nowadays by the more scientific
term,‘parapsychology’.
38.Kant affirms his belief in the notion of a ‘corpus
mysticum’at several points even in CPR, as when he says that"if
we could intuit ourselves and things as they are, we should seeourselves in a
world of spiritual natures, our sole and true community" (CPRp.836;
see also Ap.393-4]. Kant’s lifelongbelief in a spirit-world is demonstrated by
Manolesco (1969).
39.Sewall (1990, p.x [sic; page number should
read‘ix’]) lists several works written between 1889 and 1895 that dofocus on
Kant’s mystical tendencies. The most significant of these is DuPrel’s Kant’s
Vorlesungen über Psychologie(1889),
which contains an introduction entitled ‘Kant’s mystischeWeltanschauung’.
Sewall (1900,), translates the following passage frompp.vii-viii of that work:
"‘Dreams’... has been
interpreted as a daring venture of Kant’s genius in makingsport of
superstition; the accent has been laid on Kant’s negations, andhis affirmative
utterances have been overlooked. The ‘Lectures onPsychology’ now show ... that
these utterances were very seriouslyintended; for the affirmative portions of
the ‘Dreams’ agree verythoroughly with the lengthier exposition of the
‘Psychology’, andthe wavering attitude of Kant is here no longer
perceptible." (pp.13-4n)
40.I have intentionally presented this as the secondpurpose,
because the text of Dreams clearly regards it assuch. Nearly all interpreters
read into the text their own exclusiveinterest in Kant’s metaphysics,
and thereby treat the whole topic ofmystical visions as a mere (perhaps
ill-chosen) illustration. How easy it is toforget that even the title specifies
the maintopic as focusing on visionary dreams (i.e., what we would now
classify as partof parapsychology), and explicitly regards metaphysicsas
a secondary illustration.
JohanL.F.
Gerding (1994) is an exception. He stresses that Kant is dealing withparapsychological
phenomena (‘psi’). However, he takes Dreamsas a "fundamental denial
of psi" claiming "Kant explicitlystates that psi phenomena cannot
exist" (p.141). But this is too strong.Kant’s conclusion is that we cannot
form such experiences into a science:he openly
admits that psi phenomena do exist as immediate experiences; theproblem is that
we cannot understand them. Gerding (1994)goes
so far as to claim that for Kant "psi cannot even behypothetical"
(p.144) and that "Kant does not allow psi to be evenpossible." He
suggests we could avoid excluding psi from transcendentalphilosophy by tracing
them to "an unknown capacity of the human mind"(pp.144-5), but this
renders them uninformative: "Psi information from atranscendent world
therefore is not possible." He defends his position byarguing that a case
of ESP, for example, "has to be verifiable for livinghuman beings" in
order to be regarded as genuine (p.145). This stillleaves the process
unknowable: we can know thatsomething happens without knowing how
it happens. He thusconcludes: "the Kantian transcendental philosophy does
not excludeparanormal phenomena when they are interpreted as anomalous
phenomena, whichhappen to living human beings." What Gerding fails to
recognize is that aperspectival interpretation of Dreams enables us to
see thisas precisely Kant’s own view! The error is to think Kant himself did
notrecognize that psi can be mysterious yet entirely possible.
This etext is based on a prepublication draft of
the published version of this essay.
Send comments to: StevePq@hkbu.edu.hk
My Web Counter
identifies you as visitor number
to this page, last updated on 29 March 2011. Please
come again!
Back to the listing of Steve Palmquist's published
articles.
Back to the
main map of Steve
Palmquist's web site.